346
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075 Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
Moving forward in the ethical consideration of invertebrates
in experimentation: Beyond the Three R’s Principle
Augusto C. Crespi-Abril
1,3
*
Tamara Rubilar
2,3
1. Instituto Patagónico del Mar, Universidad Nacional del a Patagonia San Juan Bosco, Boulevard Brown, Puerto
Madryn, Argentina; crespi@cenpat-conicet.gob.ar (*Correspondence).
2. Laboratorio de Química de Organismos Marinos, Instituto Patagónico del Mar. Facultad de Ciencias Naturales y
Ciencias de la Salud. Universidad Nacional de la Patagonia San Juan Bosco. Bv. Brown, Puerto Madryn, Chubut,
Argentina; rubilar@cenpat-conicet.gob.ar
3. Laboratorio de Oceanografía Biológica, Centro para el Estudio de Sistemas Marinos. Boulevard Brown, Puerto
Madryn, Argentina.
Received 11-VII-2020. Corrected 24-X-2020. Accepted 06-XI-2020.
ABSTRACT
Introduction: The Three R´s Principle (Refinement, Reduction, and Replacement), postulated more than 60
years ago, is the main ethical framework currently applied for conducting animal research. This principle has
never been reviewed applying a philosophical reflection during all of these years, even though a variety of ani-
mal ethics studies have presented new insights. The Three R´s Principle was designed to be used as a policy tool
to ameliorate the suffering of animals and to reduce the use of animals in research, but has failed in achieving
these goals. This principle is only applied when using sentience vertebrates, and fails to consider invertebrates
as their capacity to sentience is still disputed. In this way, invertebrates are reified, which has been determined
to be detrimental as their suffering has been consistently denied. As a consequence, new insights are necessary
to improve scientific practices. Epistemology and ethics have always been viewed as opposing approaches.
´Epistemology-based Ethics’ subordinate ethical concern to scientific facts and ‘Ethics-based Epistemology’
purports that ethical practice should guide epistemological practices. Objective: In this paper, we maintain
that unifying both approaches under a broader conceptual framework may result in the view that these are not,
actually, opposite approaches. We propose to progress beyond the Three R’s Principle and extend it to a posi-
tion equal to the level of the ethical and epistemological approaches. We also propose to use the Precautionary
Principle as it is always better to be safe than sorry, and to include two more Rs. Methods: This paper is based
on the analysis of different ethical frameworks used in biology and ecology that can be implemented in inver-
tebrates experimentation. Results: The analysis revealed that different ethical approaches are frequently used
in biological research, but not all of them are implemented in experimental research that involves invertebrates.
We argue that the ethical considerations used in any research field can be implemented in invertebrate research.
Conclusion: We propose a Five R´s Principle: the traditional Refinement, Reduction, and Replacement, used
along with Respect and Responsibility (a respectful relationship with every living being regardless of its com-
plexity and personal commitment to conscientiously apply ethics concepts).
Key words: five R´s Principle; responsibility; respect; precautionary principle; animal ethics.
Crespi-Abril, A.C., & Rubilar, T. (2021). Moving forward
in the ethical consideration of invertebrates in
experimentation: Beyond the Three R’s Principle.
Revista de Biología Tropical, 69(S1), 346-357. DOI
10.15517/rbt.v69iSuppl.1.46366
DOI 10.15517/rbt.v69iSuppl.1.46366
347
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075, Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
Non-human animals (hereinafter referred
to as animals) have been used in experiments
for more than two thousand years. The majority
of these experiments were done on vertebrate
animals (and some in cases on invertebrates)
as they were considered adequate models of
human anatomy and physiology (von Staden,
1989). During many years, an anthropocentric
view dominated and animals were not con-
sidered subjects of ethical concern. However,
the relationship between humans and animals
has changed through time and ethical concern
regarding animals started to increase due to the
evident suffering animals were experiencing in
order to satisfy scientific enquiry. In this sense,
Bentham (1823) stated: “The question is not,
Can they reason? Nor, Can they talk? But, Can
they suffer?”. Although animal research was
acceptable under his utilitarian ideology (i.e., a
moral action is the one that results in the high-
est overall wellbeing for all stakeholders) as
benefits to mankind justified it, two hundreds
years later Bentham’s statement continues to
exert a great deal of influence in the debate on
animal use in the life sciences in general. The
recognition of animals’ sentience (capable of
experiencing suffering) was an important start-
ing point for the new philosophical thought
that would be crucial for the development of
new ethical perspectives concerning the moral
status of animals. Singer (1975) published his
work claiming for animal rights. This works is
a breakthrough since it provides an exhaustive
philosophical framework about ethics and ani-
mal suffering. In spite of its solid philosophical
ground, Singers ideas were controversial, but
they inspired a rising public concern about
animal rights that influenced animal experi-
ments (Horta, 2011). Currently, debate on
animals rights are on the table (Regan, 2003;
Regan, 2004) and significant progress has been
made at the normative level with the inclusion
of some groups of invertebrates (European
Parliament, 2010).
In 1959, Russell & Burch published their
work “The Principles of Human Experimental
Technique” where they postulated the Three
R’s Principle (Refinement, Reduction, and
Replacement) (Russell & Burch, 1959). How-
ever, this principle was largely ignored for more
than 20 years, until Smyth (1978) reinforced
the utilization of the three R’s by postulating
“all procedures which can completely replace
the need for animal experiments, reduce the
numbers of animals required, or diminish the
amount of pain or distress suffered by animals
in meeting the essential needs of man and other
animals”. This definition is not only a restate-
ment of the Three R’s, it also places the respon-
sibility onto researchers to provide robust
evidence that can justify the use of animals in
their research.
At present, the Three R’s Principle rep-
resents the main ethical framework for con-
ducting research with animals. However, this
principle was postulate over 60 years ago and
it is addressed without any major change. Even
though it is currently used to regulate the sci-
entific use of animals (Bayne, Ramachandra,
Rivera, & Wang, 2015; Burden, Chapman,
Sewell, & Robinson, 2015), it has been recent-
ly questioned due to its limitations in consid-
ering all the cases of animal use in research
(Rubilar & Crespi-Abril, 2017; Crespi-Abril &
Rubilar 2018; Hermann & Jayne, 2019). In this
work, we provide new insights that support the
ethical consideration of the majority (if not all)
of cases in which animals are used in research.
Based on our arguments, we propose a broader
principle that can be used as an ethical frame-
work in research with animals.
Invertebrates in experiments
Invertebrates represents a heterogeneous
group of animals that consist in more than 30
phyla ranging from sponges (extremely simple
multicellular organisms) to cephalopods (organ-
isms that display complex behaviors and can
solve simple problems). Invertebrates accounts
for more than 95 % of the total species on Earth
(Kellert, 1993; Wilson, 1999) which represents
more than 1 million different species.
Invertebrates are frequently used in
experiments since they present a series of
advantages over vertebrates such as: relatively
348
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075 Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
simple to maintain and culture, simpler and
easier to manipulate organisms, shorter life
cycle (Smith, Scimeca & Mainous, 2011).
Additionally, invertebrates are considered as
adequate biological models for other species
of animals including humans (Horvarth et
al., 2013). The most recognized invertebrates
models are Drosophila melanogaster, Cae-
norhabditis elegans, Aplysia californica, sea
urchins, squids and honeybees. Significant
breakthroughs were conducted in biomedical
research using only this few groups of inverte-
brates (Wilson-Sanders, 2011).
Usually invertebrates (except for cephalo-
pods and decapods) are not included in the leg-
islation and welfare of these animals is mostly
neglected. This leads to a gap of knowledge
regarding the number of individuals used in
experiments since there is no need to record it
(Harvey-Clark, 2011). Although there are no
exact estimations, the numbers of individuals
of particular species (Drosophila melanogas-
ter, Caenorhabditis elegans, Aplysia califor-
nica) may reach millions in a single laboratory
(Harvey-Clark, 2011).
Three R’s principle: current situation
Three R’s Principle introduces the three
basic concepts of Refinement, Reduction and
Replacement which any researcher should
consider when conducting research involving
animals. Basically, Russell and Burch (1959)
defined Replacement as “any scientific method
employing non-sentient material [to] replace
methods which use conscious living verte-
brates”; Reduction as diminishing “the number
of animals used to obtain information of a
given amount and precision”; and Refinement
as a series of practices conducted to “decrease
in the incidence or severity of [...] procedures
applied to those animals which have to be
used”. These three concepts are considered
to incur the same level of significant but
were originally postulated as a sequence to
achieve the goal of total replacement as a
maxim: “[r]efinement is never enough, and we
should always seek further for reduction and
if possible replacement” (Russell & Burch,
1959). Clearly, this principle is only applied
when using vertebrates since they are the only
group of animals that are considered as sentient
animals due to their similarities with humans
in terms of the structure of the nervous system.
In this sense, the principle fails to consider
inclusion of invertebrates, whose capacity to
sentience is still disputed. A strong assumption
underlies the Three R’s: This is that non-human
animals which are lower on the zoological scale
lack sentience (Tomasik, 2014). This represents
a significant constraint, especially when it is
considered that the number (and diversity) of
invertebrates used in science is overwhelming.
Despite the worldwide acceptance of the Three
R’s as a policy tool to ameliorate the suffering
of animals and to reduce the use of animals in
research, the failure in achieving these goals
has been clearly noted (Blattner, 2019). In fact,
the number of animals used for experimental
purposes in the European Union (EU) is cur-
rently similar to the number registered in 1980s
(Taylor & Rego, 2016). The main cause of this
failure is that the language used in legislation
regarding the replacement concept is frequently
laxer that the language used in refinement.
As an example, the EU Directive 2010/63/
EU states “Member States shall ensure that,
wherever possible, a scientifically satisfactory
method or testing strategy, not entailing the
use of live non-human animals, shall be used
instead of a procedure” (European Parliament,
2010, Article 4). This implies that replacement
is only necessary if alternatives exist and are
recognized by the normative. However, this
comprises a limitation as, in practice, replace-
ment alternatives are barely recognized in
legislation and when they are, they do not
refer to replacement in an absolute sense, but
to fewer sentient animals. These conditions
fail to exhort researchers to stop using animals
in research. This, in turn, leads to an implicit
hierarchical understanding of the Three R’s in
which refinement and reduction take priority
over replacement (Gerritsen, 2015).
Relation between Ethics and Epistemol-
ogy: alternative frameworks
349
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075, Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
In this section, we introduce the main rela-
tion between ethics and epistemology, which
represents a metaethical analysis. However, it
is not the aim of this paper to address exhaus-
tively the field of metaethics.
Significant advances have been made on
ethical considerations in animal experiments.
Proof of this is seen in the fact that the Three
R’s Principle govern research practices. How-
ever, the principle is not applied to any species,
but only to those considered sentient. In this
sense, it is crucial to gather evidence to ensure
that a particular species is sentient by estab-
lishing objective criteria involving behavioral,
evolutionary and physiological considerations.
Sentience is very complex to demonstrate, and
researchers have been focused on demonstrat-
ing the existence of pain, as it is assumed to
comprise a particularly important form of
suffering (EFSA Panel on Animal Health and
Welfare, 2005). In 2012, it was published the
Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness on
which scientific community concludes that ani-
mals are conscious living beings able of expe-
riencing negative emotional sensations (pain).
The experience of pain is based on the
presence of two components: nociception
(physiological detection of nocive stimuli),
and the experience of pain (negative emotional
sensation produced after a nocive stimuli). If
either of these two components is absent, it is
assumed that there is no possibility of experi-
encing pain. If nociception is absent, stimuli
are not detected, and if emotional sensations
are absent, pain does not occur (nociceptive
reflex responses). Seven criteria are applied to
determine if individuals of a particular species
are capable of experiencing pain (Smith, 1991;
EFSA Panel on Animal Health and Welfare,
2005), and these can be summarized as follows
(Andrews et al., 2013):
1. Possession of receptors sensitive to
noxious stimuli, located in functionally
useful positions on or in the body and con-
nected by nervous pathways to the lower
parts of the nervous system
2. Possession of higher brain centres (in the
sense of integration of brain processing),
especially a structure analogous to the
human cerebral cortex
3. Possession of nervous pathways connec-
ting the nociceptive system to the higher
brain centres
4. Receptors for opioid substances found in
the central nervous system, especially the
brain
5. Analgesics modify the animal’s respon-
se to stimuli that would be painful for a
human
6. An animal’s response to stimuli that would
be painful for a human is functionally
similar to the human response (that is, the
animal responds so as to avoid or minimize
damage to its body)
7. An animal’s behavioral response persists
and it shows an unwillingness to resubmit
to a painful procedure; the animal can
learn to associate apparently non-painful
with apparently painful events
Most vertebrates fulfill these criteria and
there is no doubt as to their capacity of expe-
riencing pain. But in the case of invertebrates
this is not that clear, and it is an area of long-
standing concern and controversy (Fiorito,
1986; Mather, 2016) as the majority of the
established criteria for pain are not met. This is
a fallacious argument, as ‘absence of evidence
is not evidence of absence’. If one considers
the large biodiversity of invertebrates (Kellert,
1993; Wilson, 1999) and the large variability in
‘bauplan’ (which includes the nervous system),
it is likely that the capacity of experiencing
pain can be achieved by other mechanisms
and structures differing from those described
for vertebrates (Riebli & Reichert, 2015). For
instance, cephalopods are considered to be an
exception as it has been already assumed that
they can suffer and they were included in the
ethical normative (Andrews et al., 2013; Smith
et al., 2013; Della Rocca, Di Salvo, Giannet-
toni, & Goldberg, 2015) This applies in spite of
the fact they have a different nervous system as
compared to vertebrates. However, after much
350
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075 Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
research effort, controversy still remains due
to the inherent difficulty of demonstrating the
capacity of experiencing pain by this group of
invertebrates (Harvey-Clark, 2011). With this
framework, it is assumed that we first must
evidence that animals are capable of suffering
pain and, then, we should seek ethical consider-
ations. This approach is denominated ‘Episte-
mology-based Ethics’ and subordinates ethical
concern to scientific facts (Chandroo, Yue, &
Moccia, 2004; Griffin & Speck, 2004; Elwood,
2011; Lewbart & Mosley, 2012; Mather, 2016).
A different approach has been proposed
in which the relationship between epistemol-
ogy and ethics is inverted where: ethics should
guide epistemological practices. This implies
that there is an initial need to establish a
respectful relationship with living beings rather
than a facts-based relationship. This, implies a
limit (ethical one) on our actions, resulting in
the need to rethink whether knowledge regard-
ing the biology, physiology, ecology of animals
should take precedence over the welfare of
those living beings. In addition, it is impor-
tant to note in this context that the utilitarian
rationale purporting that human interest takes
precedence over animal suffering is an insuffi-
cient ethical justification for the use of animals
in experimentation as animals and humans
equal rights as living beings. This approach
is denominated ‘Ethics-based Epistemology’
(Cheney & Weston, 1999; Weston, 2009). This
insight has been implemented in research with
invertebrates, particularly regarding echino-
derms (Rubilar & Crespi-Abril, 2017; Crespi-
Abril & Rubilar, 2018). To biologists, this
different approach may sound counterproduc-
tive as the focus of our own research may be,
in fact invertebrates. However, we believe
that science can be exercised within a new
bio-ethical framework that includes these new
concepts and ideas.
Precautionary Principle
The precautionary principle aims to
take actions to avoid harm even though evi-
dence is insufficient to provide certainties on
the magnitude or probability of happening
(Raffensperger, 1999; Kriebel et al., 2001). A
simple way to phrase this is: until the risk of
harm is controlled, be cautious, as it is better
to be ‘safe than sorry’. This rationale guides
the vast majority of human, ordinary activi-
ties. This is not the same in current scientific
practices involving animal experiments. As we
stated above, the current approach is that until
we do have the certainty that animals are capa-
ble of experiencing suffering (harm), we will
not, ethically, give them consideration (action).
Why do we act this way in science? The answer
to this point does not rely on the fact that the
principle leads in the wrong direction, but
in the thought that it leads in no direction at
all and threatens to be paralyzing (Sunstein,
2003). This thought generates resistance in the
researcher community to start considering an
ethical approach in scientific practices. With
vertebrates there is a clear consensus on this
point, but most invertebrates are still not treated
relying on bio-ethical basis.
The precautionary principle is stated by
incorporating different levels of restrictions
that can be grouped into weak or strong ver-
sions. The weak version is less restrictive and
allows preventive actions under the existence
of the risk of harm, but does not require such
preventive actions. Often, cost-benefits analy-
ses are considered in order to postpone preven-
tive actions and these analyses include factors
other than scientific certainty, such as eco-
nomic factors. In this case, the burden of proof
(the requirements to justify) lies with those
advocating precautionary actions. On the other
hand, the strong version requires the taking of
precautionary actions in the presence of the risk
of harm, in spite of the costs incurred in doing
so. Here, the burden of proof is inverted and
lies with those who argue that certain activities
will not cause significant harm. This means
that society is not willing to accept any envi-
ronmental risk, no matter the benefits (social
or economic) that may be achieved (Di Salvo &
Raymond, 2010). Four types of the precaution-
ary principle were distinguished capturing both
weak and strong types by Stewart (2002):
351
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075, Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
Non-preclusion Precautionary Principle:
Scientific uncertainty should not automati-
cally preclude that regulation of activities
posing a potential risk of significant harm.
Margin of Safety Precautionary Principle:
Regulatory controls should incorporate a
margin of safety; activities should be limi-
ted below the level at which no adverse
effect has been observed or predicted.
Best Available Technology Precautionary
Principle: Activities that present an uncer-
tain potential for significant harm should
be subject to best technology available
requirements to minimize the risk of harm
unless the proponent of the activity shows
that they present no appreciable risk of
harm.
Prohibitory Precautionary Principle: Acti-
vities that present an uncertain potential
for significant harm should be prohibited
unless the proponent of the activity shows
that it presents no appreciable risk of harm.
Currently scientific practices involving
animal experiments are guided under a weak
precautionary principle as it is necessary to
demonstrate (to show scientific certainty) the
existence of pain (harm) in order to take
actions to diminish such pain and always only
after a cost-benefit analysis has taken place to
determine the benefit of the scientific practice.
In an opposing position, one finds the ideals
postulated by activists whose claims argue
for a strong version of precautionary principle
requiring the demonstration that pain is not
present (absence of harm). Both of these are
extreme positions and there are several flaws in
the justification of each posture. Here, we pro-
pose to reach a position in the middle ground.
Five R’s Principle:
beyond Russell´s proposal
Problems emerging from an ethical
approach regarding animal experimentation
are more widely appreciated than the episte-
mological ones. Most researchers agree that
subordinating ethics into epistemology (Epis-
temology-based Ethics), provides rigorous sci-
entific ground whilst an empathic approach
with animals (Ethic-based Epistemology) may
bias experiments and conclusions due to the
extreme reduction in the number of animals
used or to the use of inappropriate replace-
ments. In this way, it is assumed that keep-
ing ethics out of the picture will provide the
objectivity that is crucial for science. However,
researcher desensitization may bias the results
of experiments as animals may be kept in inap-
propriate environmental conditions (e.g. small
spaces, intense noise, lack of environmental
stimulation, poor quality of seawater, under
fed, etc.) which produce significant levels of
stress in the animals. This causes epistemologi-
cal problems as stress impacts on the physiol-
ogy of individuals, hence, modifying their
response to treatments and, thereby, affecting
the reliability of scientific data obtained from
the animals (Baldwin, Primeau & Johnson,
2006; Burwell & Baldwin, 2006). None of
these approaches are completely satisfactory
since they present flaws, either at the episte-
mological level or ethical level. Consequently,
there is no difference in our choice of levels to
guide our scientific practices; in either case, we
will not be able to fulfill epistemological and
ethical grounds. One important point that is
supposed to be a barrier in this context is that
both approaches are seen to comprise oppo-
site and irreconcilable frameworks, instead
of complementary. We maintain that unifying
both approaches under a broader conceptual
framework may lead to the possibility of over-
coming previous flaws.
The Three Rs’ Principle was thought to
provide ethical grounds (although limited only
to certain species) for animal experimentation,
but were not to address the epistemological
problems arising from animal manipulation
(Johnson & Degeling, 2012). We maintain that
this principle needs to be extended in order to
unify both approaches into a broader concep-
tual framework that considers the ethical and
epistemological grounds at the same level here
proposed to expand the principle including
352
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075 Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
two concepts involving personal commitment:
Respect and Responsibility (Fig. 1).
Respect
Respect points to the establishment a
respectful relationship with any living beings,
regardless of their complexity or the knowl-
edge we have of them. This implies that we
are to be respectful with life, itself, rather
than being in a facts-based relationship. The
use of animals in experimentation implies a
restriction on the ethical consideration to them.
This not only implies leaving out from ethical
consideration several individuals (such as any
invertebrate), but also implies the restriction of
our ethical actions to those animals which are
considered ethically (e.g. individual suffering
is justified if it is in favor of human benefits).
Researchers often carry out procedures that
have been defined and required by others (such
as institutions or colleagues), which means
that their ethical autonomy is not considered
when conducting experiments with animals.
They are trained to desensitize, by reframing
their ethical relationship with animals, in order
to accomplish the job when it involves ani-
mal experiments, as these experiments always
imply animal suffering (Capaldo, 2004). At this
point, researchers are no longer empathetically
related with animals but, instead, take a neutral
observer perspective, intentionally avoiding
any commitment with them. This perspective
distorts the ability to relate to animals by pro-
moting reification of them (Honneth, 2006).
Reification is very risky for those who are
reified, since their interests or suffering are per-
manently denied (Johnson & Smajdor, 2019).
An empathic relationship with animals
does not imply a barrier to achieving knowl-
edge about them or to the use of the animals
according to our needs. Although an empathic
relationship in science is an innovative insight,
it is worth noting that it is not fanciful or
implausible, and is therefore a strategy that is
worth considering. There are solid evidences
among empathic relation and emotions com-
munication between mammals and this could
provide a novel field for studying empathic
relations in other animals groups (Preston & de
Wall, 2002; de Waal & Preston, 2017). There
are two different approaches in which the key
point is empathy. These are the Traditional
Ecological Knowledge (TEK) and Animal-
as-Patients approaches. The first one involves
three aspects of nature: the cosmos (beliefs,
emotions and symbolic representations), the
corpus (general environmental knowledge),
and the praxis (the behaviors carried out in
relation to the use of Nature). Advances com-
ing from ethnoecology revealed that several
cultures relate with environment in a respect-
ful manner (Toledo & Barrera-Bassols, 2008).
They consider that environment is populated
by living beings that have social relation-
ships between themselves and with whom they
establish social relationships. This provides a
conceptual framework allowing a responsible
management of natural resources, transcending
mere utilitarian and economic aspects (Gadgil,
Berkes, & Folke, 1993; Berkes, Colding, &
Folke, 2000). This implies a type of knowledge
that can be fully understood only if symbol-
isms and meanings that are attributed to natural
entities are considered (Reyes-García & Martí,
2007). The second one, is to approach animals
during experiments as patients (Pemberton,
2004; Haraway, 2008). This means to shift our
current actions undertaken during experiments
to treating animals as individual patients rather
than as mass-produced and expendable objects.
This means that animals should be included
in experiments in a similar way as humans
are enrolled into clinical trials (Johnson &
Degeling, 2012). This approach is already
implemented in animal experimentation in vet-
erinary practice. When an animal is put through
an experimental treatment, the care and welfare
of the individual is not only evaluated by the
neutral (professional) position of the veterinar-
ian, but also by the empathy and feelings of
the owner.
353
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075, Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
Responsibility
Responsibility when conducting animal
experiments is the fifth concept that completes
our proposal. The essence of scientific work
requires a strong professional ethics since
it is based on the confidence of the scien-
tific community in the honesty of research-
ers. Although there is a rigorous peer review
process, honesty in performing experiments,
conducting data analysis and reporting the
results is crucial. We argue in favor of expand-
ing this responsibility and of including ethical
commitment with animals as a part of our prac-
tices. Responsibility has already invoked by
the Max Planck Society (MPG, 2020), mainly
focusing on promoting animal welfare. In our
proposal, responsibility calls for the personal
commitment of researchers to conscientiously
apply the ethical concepts. This goes beyond
just promoting welfare, but also promotes the
rethinking as to whether knowledge regarding
the biology, physiology, ecology or medicine
should be prioritized over the welfare of the
animals involved in experiments. We need to
act responsibly when using animals in experi-
ments considering the real value of the life of
each living being, and we need to be honest
when asking if the life of any animal worth the
knowledge obtained. The most controversial
point is, of course, the use of animal experi-
ments in medicine (Knight, 2019). There is a
long tradition in using animals as physiological
models in medicine, and currently this is an
unavoidable step in medical trials in spite of
the fact that there is overwhelming evidence
that animals are not appropriate models (Ram,
2019). The unquestioned practice of using
animals in medicine not only has ethical con-
cerns, but also implies a problem in terms of
human health (Greek & Kramer, 2019). This
is a clear example of a scientific practice that
can not stand a critical and responsible review
and would need to be abandoned in most cases
(Archibald, Coleman, & Drake, 2019).
Concluding Remarks
The current framework allows researchers
to relieve their ethical commitment through
the implementation of the Three R’s Prin-
ciple. However, this is not enough for ethically
responsible science. The Three R’s Principle
comprised a starting point in establishing an
ethical approach in science but has remained
almost unmodified for more than 60 years.
As a community, we owe a critical review of
our approaches to animals in experiments. It
is necessary to keep permanently revising our
approaches in order to develop new insights.
We propose to extended the Three R Principle
to a position in which the ethical and episte-
mological approaches are at the same level.
This change may seem difficult to implement,
but this should not be a barrier to developing
new ways of thinking. All significant changes
were seen as impossible when first postulated
and are now commonplace. Scientific practice
is no exception to the rule, it is worth to keep
promoting ethical concern and real commit-
ment in terms of how researchers relate to ani-
mals in the context of their own work and how
this can be improved. We must stop accepting
practices that in the long-term perpetuate the
use of animals in experiments as an accept-
able scientific standard. We are aware that
this may not be seen as a straightforward way
Fig. 1. Five R´s Principle. Equal level of importance of the
ethical and epistemological approaches.
354
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075 Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
of implementing changes, but communication
between stakeholders (e.g. researchers, vet-
erinarians, animal welfare activists, competent
authorities) is crucial to promote change and
keep moving forward on ethical commitment in
animal experimentation. It is very important to
include whole society in the debate since public
perception and opinion is a strong influence in
defining scientific practices and it is a chal-
lenge in invertebrates research (Drinkwater,
Robinson, & Hart, 2019).
We propose to use the Precautionary Prin-
ciple along with the Five R´s Principle, includ-
ing Refinement, Reduction, Replacement but
also Respect (to establish a respectful rela-
tionship with any living being regardless its
complexity or the knowledge we have of
that living being) and Responsibility (personal
commitment of researchers to conscientiously
apply ethics concepts). Under this new pro-
posal, invertebrates are at the same level of
ethical concern as vertebrates. This means that
institutional animal care and use committee
(IACUC) should evaluate all research project
that requires the use of any invertebrate, and
not only those projects that involves verte-
brates. The high diversity of invertebrates
requires that IACUC address with particular
attention every case and this challenging for
committee members (Harvey-Clark, 2001).
However, in order for our proposal to succeed,
it must be embraced in all of the different roles
we as researchers assume and execute. First, in
our own practices in the laboratory, then in our
teaching (e.g. universities, schools, courses,
etc) but, most crucially, in our role as review-
ers. We can change the balance within and shift
our own practices, but we can do even more in
influencing others to follow in our tracks and,
in the manner, initiate a real change.
Ethical statement: authors declare that
they all agree with this publication and made
significant contributions; that there is no con-
flict of interest of any kind; and that we fol-
lowed all pertinent ethical and legal procedures
and requirements. All financial sources are fully
and clearly stated in the acknowledgements
section. A signed document has been filed in
the journal archives.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
We would like to thanks to Kathleen
Anderson for the revision of the English and
criticism of the manuscript. In addition, we
thank the anonymous reviewers for their
comments, which improved significantly the
manuscript.
RESUMEN
Avanzando sobre la consideración ética
de los invertebrados en experimentación:
más allá del principio de las tres Rs
Introducción: El Principio de las Tres R (Refina-
miento, Reducción y Reemplazo), postulado hace más
de 60 años, es el principal marco ético que se aplica
actualmente para realizar investigaciones en animales. Este
principio no ha sido revisado desde una reflexión filosófica
a pesar de tantos años y de lavariedad de estudios en ética
animal que han presentado nuevas ideas. Este principio
solo se aplica cuando se utilizan vertebrados sintientes,
y no tiene en cuenta a los invertebrados, ya que su capa-
cidad de sentiencia aún está cuestinada. De esta manera,
los invertebrados son cosificados, lo que ha sido en su
detrimento ya que su sufrimiento ha sido constantemente
negado. El Principio de las Tres R fue diseñado para ser
utilizado como una herramienta de política para mejorar
el sufrimiento de los animales y reducir el uso de anima-
les en la investigación, pero no ha logrado alcanzar estos
objetivos. Como consecuencia, se necesitan nuevas ideas
para mejorar las prácticas científicas. La epistemología y
la ética siempre se han visto como enfoques opuestos. La
concepción ética subordinada de a los hechos científicos se
llama “Ética basada en la epistemología” y, en cambio, la
“Epistemología basada en la ética” pretende que la práctica
ética guie las prácticas epistemológicas. Objetivo: En este
trabajo, proponemos que unificar ambos enfoques bajo un
marco conceptual más amplio y eliminar la percepción
de que son enfoques opuestos. Proponemos avanzar más
allá del Principio de las Tres R , extenderlo y colocar
un mismo nivel a los enfoques éticos y epistemológicos.
También proponemos utilizar el Principio de precaución,
ya que siempre es mejor prevenir que curar e incluir dos
R más. Métodos: El trabajo está basado en un análisis de
diferentes corrientes éticas utilizadas en biología y ecología
que pueden ser implementadas en la experimentación con
invertebrados. Resultados: El análisis de los trabajos reve-
ló que hay diferentes posturas éticas que se usan frecuente-
mente en biología, pero no todas ellas son implementadas
355
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075, Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
en la experimentación con invertebrados. Bajos nuestra
argumentación sostenemos que las consideraciones éticas
usadas en cualquier campo de investigación puede ser
implementada en la experimentación con invertebrados.
Conclusión: De esta manera, proponemos un Principio de
las Cinco R: Refinamiento, Reducción, Reemplazo para
ser usados junto con el Respeto y la Responsabilidad (una
relación respetuosa con cada ser vivo independientemente
de su complejidad y un compromiso personal de aplicar
conscientemente los conceptos éticos).
Palabras clave: principio de las Cinco R; responsabilidad;
respeto; principio de precaución; ética; epistemología.
REFERENCES
Andrews, P.L., Darmaillacq, A.S., Dennison, N., Gleadall,
I.G., Hawkins, P., Messenger, J. B., … Smith, J.A.
(2013). The identification and management of pain,
suffering and distress in cephalopods, including
anaesthesia, analgesia and humane killing. Journal
of Experimental Marine Biology and Ecology, 447,
46-64.
Archibald, K., Coleman, R., & Drake, T. (2019). Replacing
animal tests to improve safety for humans. In K. Her-
mann & K. Jayne (Eds.), Animal Experimentation:
Working Towards a Paradigm Change (pp. 417-442).
The Netherlands: Brill.
Baldwin, A.L., Primeau, R.L., & Johnson, W.E. (2006).
Effect of Noise on the Morphology of the Intestinal
Mucosa in Laboratory Rats. Journal of the American
Association for Laboratory Animal Science, 45(1),
74-82
Bayne, K., Ramachandra, G.S., Rivera, E.A., & Wang, J.
(2015). The evolution of animal welfare and the 3Rs
in Brazil, China, and India. Journal of the American
Association for Laboratory Animal Science, 54(2),
181-191.
Bentham, J. (1823). An Introduction to the Principles of
Morals and Legislation. London, UK: W. Pickering.
Berkes, F., Colding, J., & Folke, C. (2000). Rediscovery of
traditional ecological knowledge as adaptive Mana-
gement. Ecological Application, 10, 1251-1262.
Blattner, C.E. (2019). Rethinking the 3Rs: From whitewas-
hing to rights. In K. Hermann & K. Jayne (Eds.), Ani-
mal Experimentation: Working towards a paradigm
change (pp. 168-193). The Netherlands: Brill.
Burden, N., Chapman, K., Sewell, F., & Robinson, V.
(2015). Pioneering Better Science through the 3Rs:
An Introduction to the National Centre for the Repla-
cement, Refinement, and Reduction of Animals in
Research (NC3Rs). Journal of the American Associa-
tion for Laboratory Animal Science, 54(2), 198-208.
Burwell, A.K., & Baldwin, A.L. (2006). Do Audible and
Ultrasonic Sounds of Intensities Common in Animal
Facilities Affect the Autonomic Nervous System of
Rodents?. Journal of Applied Animal Welfare Scien-
ce, 9(3), 179-200.
Capaldo, T. (2004) The psychological effects on students of
using animals in ways that they see as ethically, mora-
lly, or religiously wrong. Alternatives to Laboratory
Animals, 1(32), 525-532.
Chandroo, K.P., Duncan, I.J., & Moccia, R.D. (2004). Can
fish suffer? Perspectives on sentience, pain, fear and
stress. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 86(3),
225-250.
Cheney, J., & Weston, A. (1999). Environmental ethics
as environmental etiquette: Toward an ethics-based
epistemology. Environmental Ethics, 21(2), 115-134.
Crespi-Abril, A.C., & Rubilar, T. (2018). Ética e inver-
tebrados: análisis de los casos de los cefalópodos y
equinodermos. Revista Latinoamericana de Estudios
Críticos Animales, 8, 210-232.
de Waal, F. B., & Preston, S. D. (2017). Mammalian
empathy: behavioural manifestations and neural
basis. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 18(8), 498-509.
Della Rocca, G., Di Salvo, A., Giannettoni, G., & Gold-
berg, M.E. (2015). Pain and suffering in invertebra-
tes: an insight on cephalopods. American Journal of
Animal and Veterinary Sciences, 10(2), 77.
Di Salvo, C.P., & Raymond, L. (2010). Defining the pre-
cautionary principle: an empirical analysis of elite
discourse. Environmental Politics, 19(1), 86-106.
Drinkwater, E., Robinson, E.J., & Hart, A.G. (2019).
Keeping invertebrate research ethical in a landscape
of shifting public opinion. Methods in Ecology and
Evolution, 10(8), 1265-1273.
EFSA Panel on Animal Health and Welfare (2005). Opi-
nion of the Scientific Panel on Animal Health and
Welfare (AHAW) on a request from the Commission
related to the “Aspects of the biology and welfare of
animals used for experimental and other scientific
purposes”. EFSA J. 292, 1-136.
Elwood, R.W. (2011). Pain and suffering in invertebrates?.
Ilar Journal, 52(2), 175-184.
European Parliament. (2010). Directive 2010/63/EU of
the European Parliament and of the Council of
22 September 2010 on the protection of animals
used for scientific purposes. Official Journal of the
European Communities, L276, pp. 33–79. [online]
Available at: http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/
EN/TXT/?uri=CELEX%3A32010L0063 [Accessed
4 September 2020].
Fiorito, G. (1986). Is there “pain” in Invertebrates?. Beha-
vioral Proceeding, 12, 383-388.
356
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075 Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
Gadgil, M., Berkes, F., & Folke, C. (1993). Indigenous
knowledge for biodiversity conservation. Ambio 22,
151-6.
Gerritsen, V. (2015). Evaluation Process for Animal Expe-
riment Applications in Switzerland. Alternatives to
Animal Experimentation: Proceedings, 4(1), 37-40.
Greek, R., & Kramer, L.A. (2019). The scientific problems
with using non-human animals to predict human
response to drugs and disease. In K. Hermann &
K. Jayne (Eds.), Animal Experimentation: Working
towards a paradigm change (pp. 391-416). The
Netherlands: Brill.
Griffin, D.R., & Speck, G.B. (2004). New evidence of
animal consciousness. Animal cognition, 7(1), 5-18.
Haraway, D.J. (2008). When Species Meet. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Harvey-Clark, C. (2011). IACUC challenges in invertebra-
te research. Ilar Journal, 52(2), 213-220.
Hermann, K., & Jayne, K. (2019). Animal Experimenta-
tion: Working Towards a Paradigm Change. The
Netherlands: Brill.
Honneth, A. (2006). Reification: A Recognition Theoretical
View. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Berke-
ley: University of California.
Horta, O. (2011). La argumentación de Singer en Libe-
ración animal: concepciones normativas, interés en
vivir y agregacionismo. Diánoia, 56(67), 65-85.
Horvath, K., Angeletti, D., Nascetti, G., & Carere, C.
(2013). Invertebrate welfare: an overlooked issue.
Annali dell’Istituto superiore di sanità, 49, 9-17.
Johnson, J., & Degeling, C. (2012). Animals-as-Patients:
Improving the Practice of Animal Experimentation.
Between the Species, 15(1), 43-58.
Johnson, J., & Smajdor, A. (2019). Human Wrongs in
Animal Research: A Focus on Moral Injury and Rei-
fication. Human-Animal Studies. In K. Hermann &
K. Jayne (Eds.), Animal Experimentation: Working
towards a paradigm change (pp. 305-317). The
Netherlands: Brill.
Kellert, S.R. (1993). Values and perceptions of invertebra-
tes. Conservation biology, 7(4), 845-855.
Knight, A. (2019). Critically evaluating animal research.
In K. Hermann & K. Jayne (Eds.), Animal Experi-
mentation: Working towards a paradigm change (pp.
321-340). The Netherlands: Brill.
Kriebel, D., Tickner, J., Epstein, P., Lemons, J., Levins, R.,
Loechler, E.L., & Stoto, M. (2001). The precautio-
nary principle in environmental science. Environmen-
tal health perspectives, 109(9), 871-876.
Lewbart, G.A., & Mosley, C. (2012). Clinical anesthesia
and analgesia in invertebrates. Journal of exotic pet
medicine, 21(1), 59-70.
Mather, J.A. (2016). An invertebrate perspective on pain.
Animal Sentience: An Interdisciplinary Journal on
Animal Feeling, 1(3), 12.
MPG. (2020). Reduce, refine, replace – responsibility. Max
Planck Society. [online] Available at: https://www.
mpg.de/10973438/4rs [Accessed 4 September 2020].
Pemberton, S. (2004). Canine technologies, model patients:
The historical production of hemophiliac dogs. In S.
Shrepfer & P. Scranton (Eds.), American Biomedici-
ne. In Industrializing Organisms (pp. 191- 213). New
York: Routledge.
Preston, S. D. & de Waal, F. B. M. (2002). The communi-
cation of emotions and the possibility of empathy in
animals. In: S. Post, L. G. Underwood, J. P. Schloss,
& W. B. Hurlburt (Eds.), Altruistic love: Science,
philosophy, and religion in dialogue. (pp. 284–308).
Oxford, UK: Oxford Univ. Press
Raffensperger, C., & Tickner J. (1999). Protecting public
health and the environment: Implementing the pre-
cautionary principle. Washington, D.C.: Island Press.
Ram, R. (2019). Extrapolation of animal research data to
humans: an analysis of the evidence. In K. Hermann
& K. Jayne (Eds.), Animal Experimentation: Working
towards a paradigm change (pp. 341-375). The
Netherlands: Brill.
Regan, T. (2003). Animal rights, human wrongs: an intro-
duction to moral philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield.
Regan, T. (2004). The case for animal rights. Univ of
California Press.
Reyes-García V., & Martí, S.N. (2007) Etnoecología: punto
de encuentro entre naturaleza y cultura. Ecosistemas,
16(3), 46-55.
Riebli, N., & Reichert, H. (2015). Perspective - The first
brain. In A. Schmidt-Rhaesa, S. Harzsch & G. Purs-
chke (Eds.), Structure and Evolution of Invertebrate
Nervous System (p. 67-74). Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press.
Rubilar, T., & Crespi-Abril, A. (2017). Does Echinoderm
research deserve an ethical consideration?. Revista de
Biología Tropical, 65, 11-22.
Russell, W.M.S., & Burch, R.L. (1959). The principles
of humane experimental technique. London, UK:
Methuen & Co. Ltd.
Singer, P (1975). Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for our
Treatment of Animals. New York Review/Random
House, New York.
357
Revista de Biología Tropical, ISSN electrónico: 2215-2075, Vol. 69(S1): 346-357, March 2021 (Published Mar. 30, 2021)
Smith, J. (1991). The ethics of using animals in biome-
dical research: the findings of a working party of
the Institute of Medical Ethics. Bulletin of medical
ethics, 13-17.
Smith, J.A., Andrews, P.L.R., Hawkins, P., Louhimies, S.,
Ponte, G., & Dickel, L. (2013). Cephalopod research
and EU Directive 2010/63/EU: Requirements,
impacts and ethical review. Journal of Experimental
Marine Biology and Ecology, 447, 31-45.
Smith, S.A., Scimeca, J.M., & Mainous, M.E. (2011).
Culture and maintenance of selected invertebrates in
the laboratory and classroom. ILAR journal, 52(2),
153-164.
Smyth, D.H. (1978). Alternatives to Animal Experiments.
London, UK: Scholar Press [for] the Research Defen-
se Society.
Stewart, R.B. (2002). Environmental regulatory decision
making under uncertainty. Research in Law and Eco-
nomics, 20, 71-126.
Sunstein, C.R. (2003). Beyond the precautionary principle.
University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 151(3),
1003-1058.
Taylor, K., & Rego, L. (2016). EU statistics on animal
experiments for 2014. ALTEX, 33(4), 465-468.
Toledo, V.M., & Barrera-Bassols, N. (2008). La memoria
biocultural. La importancia ecológica de las sabidu-
rías tradicionales. Barcelona: Icaria.
Tomasik, B. (2014). Suffering in Animals vs. humans, essays
on reducing suffering. Retrieved from http://redu-
cing-suffering.org/suffering-in-animals-vs-humans/
Von Staden, H. (1989). Herophilus: The Art of Medicine
in Early Alexandria. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Weston, A. (2009). The incomplete eco-philosopher:
Essays from the edges of environmental ethics. Nueva
York: SUNY Press.
Wilson, E.O. (1999). The diversity of life. Harvard: Har-
vard University Press.
Wilson-Sanders, S.E. (2011). Invertebrate models for
biomedical research, testing, and education. ILAR
journal, 52(2), 126-152.