Abstract
En el presente trabajo indagamos en una concepción cognitiva del lenguaje a través de un examen de la “hipótesis del recableado” propuesta por Bermúdez (2005), según la cual la adquisición del lenguaje (tanto en la ontogenia como en la filogenia) genera una profunda reestructuración de la arquitectura de la cognición, haciendo posibles nuevas formas de procesamiento y representación. Con el fin de evaluar esta hipótesis, exploramos sus dimensiones ontogénica y filogénica, concluyéndose que la evidencia disponible solo respalda cierta versión filogénica de esta hipótesis. Más precisamente, que durante la evolución del lenguaje se habría “recableado” la cognición haciendo posible la capacidad de meta-representación, en tanto que durante la adquisición de una lengua no se produce una reconfiguración sustantiva de la arquitectura de la cognición.
Literaturhinweise
Abotiz, F., García, R., Brunetti, E., y Bosman, C. (2006). The origin of Broca ́s area and its connections from an ancestral working memory network. En Broca ́s Region (pp. 3–16). Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Allen, C., y Bekoff, M. (1997). Species of mind: The philosophy and biology of cognitive ethology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Au, T. (1999). Language and thought. En R. A. Wilson y F.C. Keil (Eds.), The MIT Encyclopedia of The Cognitive Sciences (pp. 444-446). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Baddeley, A. (1986). Working Memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Baillargeon, R. (2004). Infants’ reasoning about hidden objects: evidence for event-general and event-specific expectations. Developmental Science. 7 (4), 391–424.
Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 22 (4), 577–660.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2003). Thinking without words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2005). Philosophy of psychology: A contemporary introduction. Nueva York: Routledge.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2009). Mind reading in the animal kingdom. En R. Lurz (Ed.), The Philosophy of Animal Minds (pp. 145–164). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bermúdez, J. L. (2010). Two Arguments for the Language-Dependence of Thought. En J. Langkau y C. Nimtz (Eds.), New Perspectives On Concepts (pp. 37–54). Amsterdam: Editions Rodopi.
Berwick, R. C., Friederici, A. D., Chomsky, N., y Bolhuis, J. J. (2013). Evolution, brain, and the nature of language. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 17 (2), 89–98.
Botterill, G., & Carruthers, P. (1999). The philosophy of psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. (1996). Language, Thought and Consciousness: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. (2013). Animal minds are real, (distinctively) human minds are not. American Philosophical Quarterly. 50 (3), 233–248.
Carruthers, P., y Boucher, J. (1998). Introduction: opening up options. En P. Carruthers y J. Boucher (Eds.), Language And Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes (pp. 1–18). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ Press.
Clark, A. (1997). Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (1998). Magic Words: How Language Augments Human Computation. En P. Carruthers y J. Boucher (Eds.), Language And Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes (pp. 162–183). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Clayton, N., Bussey, T., y Dickinson, A. (2003). Can animals recall the past and plan for the future? Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 4, 685–691.
Cheney, D., y Seyfarth, R. (2007). Baboon metaphysics: The evolution of a social mind. Chigago: University of Chicago Press.
Davidson, D. (1982). Rational Animals. Dialectica. 36, 318–327.
Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Deacon, T. (1997). The Symbolic Species. Nueva York: Norton.
Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Allen Lane: Penguin Books.
Flombaum, J., y Santos, L. (2005). Rhesus monkeys attribute perceptions to others. Current Biology. 15, 447–452.
Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay in faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (2003). Review of Bermúdez’s “Thinking without words.” London Review of Books. 25 (19), 16–17.
Frankish, K. (1998). Natural language and virtual belief. En P. Carruthers y J. Boucher (Eds.), Language And Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes (pp. 248–269). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learning. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.
Gallistel, C. R. (2009). The foundational abstractions. En M. Piattelli-Palmirini, J. Uriagereka, y P. Salaburu (Eds.), Of minds and language: A dialogue with Noam Chomsky in the Basque Country (pp. 58–73). Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Goldin-Meadow, S. (2003). Thought before language: do we think ergative? En D. Gentner y S. Goldin-Meadow (Eds.), Language in mind: advances in the study of language and thought (pp. 493–522). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Goldin-Meadow, S., y Zheng, M.-Y. (1998). Thought before language: the expression of motion events prior to the impact of a conventional language system. En P. Carruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Language And Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes (pp. 26–54). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gomila, A. (2012). Verbal Minds: Language and the Architecture of Cognition. Londres: Elsevier Science.
Gould, J. L., y Gould, C. G. (1994). The animal mind. Nueva York: NY: Scientific American Library.
Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N., y Fitch, W. T. (2002). The faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve? Science. 298(5598), 1569–1579.
Heil, J. (2009). Language and Thought. En B. Mclaughlin, A. Beckermann, y S. Walter (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind (pp. 631–647). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hunt, E., y Agnoli, F. (1991). The Whorfian hypothesis: a cognitive psychology perspective. Psychological Review. 98, 377–389.
Hurford, J. (2003). The language mosaic and its evolution. En M. Christiansen y S. Kirby (Eds.), Language evolution: states of the art (pp. 38–57). Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1995). Beyond Modularity: A Developmental Perspective on Cognitive Science. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Kirby, S., y Christiansen, M. (2003). From languaje learning to language evolution. En Language evolution: states of the art (pp. 272-294). Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Kuczaj, S., y Hendry, J. (2003). Does Language Help Animals Think? En D. Gentner y S. Goldin-Meadow (Eds.), Language in mind: advances in the study of language and thought (pp. 237–276). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Liszkowski, U., Schäfer, M., Carpenter, M., y Tomasello, M. (2009). Prelinguistic infants , but not chimpanzees, communicate about absent entities. Psychological Science. 20 (5), 654–660.
Lucy, J. (1997). Linguistic relativity. Annual Review of Anthropology. 26, 291–312.
MacWinney, B. (1999). The emergence of language from embodiment. En B. MacWinney (Ed.), The emergence of language (pp. 213–256). Nueva York: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.
Machery, E. (2005). You don’t know how you think: Introspection and language of thought. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 56 (3), 469–485.
Machery, E. (2010). Replies to my critics. Philosophical Studies. 149, 429–436.
Malle, B. F. (2002). The relation between language and theory of mind in development and evolution. En T. Givón y B. F. Malle (Eds.), The evolution of language out of pre-language (pp. 265–284). Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Mccrink, K., y Wynn, K. (2004). Large-Number Addition and Subtraction by 9-Month-Old Infants. Psychological Science. 15 (11), 776–781.
McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Harvard: Harvard University Press.
Mithen, S. (1996). The Prehistory of the Mind. Londres: Thames And Hudson.
Penn, D. C., Holyoak, K. J., y Povinelli, D. J. (2008). Darwin’s mistake: explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 31 (2), 109–30. DOI:10.1017/S0140525X08003543.
Perner, J. (1998). The meta-intentional nature of executive functions and theory of mind. En P. Carruthers y J. Boucher (Eds.), Language And Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes (pp. 270–284). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Petitto, L.-A. (2005). How the brain begets language. En J. McGilvray (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Chomsky (pp. 84–101). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pinker, S. (1994). The Language Instinct. Londres: Penguin Books.
Pinker, S., y Bloom, P. (1990). Natural language and natural selection. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 13 (4), 707–784.
Povinelli, D. J. (2001). On the possibilities of detecting intentions prior to undestanding them. En B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, y D. A. Baldwin (Eds.), Intentions and intentionality: foundations of social cognition (pp. 225–248). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Preuss, T. (2011). The human brain: rewired and running hot. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 1225 (Suppl 1), 1–15.
Prinz, J. J. (2002). Furnishing the mind: concept s and their perceptual basis. Cambridge Mass: MIT Press.
Proust, J. (2013). The philosophy of metacognition: mental agency and self-awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Savage-Rumbaugh, S. McDonald, K., Sevcik, R. A., Hopkins, W. D., y Rubert, E. (1986). Spontaneous symbol acquisition and communicative use by pygmy chimpanzees (Pan paniscus). Journal of Experimental Psychology. 115, 211–235.
Shettleworth, S. (1998). Cognition, evolution, and behavior. Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Shettleworth, S. J. (2001). Animal cognition and animal behaviour. Animal Behaviour. 61 (2), 277–286.
Smith, J. D., Shields, W. E., y Washburn, D. A. (2003). The comparative psychology of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 26, 317–373.
Spelke, E. S., Phillips, A., y Woodward, A. L. (1995). Infants’ knowledge of object motion and human action. En D. Sperber, D. Premack, y A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 44–78). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sperber, D. (2000). Metarepresentations in an Evolutionary Perspective. En D. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresentations: A Multidisciplinary Perspective (pp. 117–138). Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Terrace, H. (2005). Metacognition and the evolution of language. In H. Terrace & J. Metcalfe (Eds.), The missing link in cognition: Origins of self-reflective consciousness (pp. 84–115). Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Tetzlaff, M., y Rey, G. (2009). Systematicity and intentional realism in honeybee navigation. En R. Lurz (Ed.), The philosophy of animal minds (pp. 72–88). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., y Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: the origins of cultural cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 28 (05), 675–691.
Tomasello, M., y Call, J. (1997). Primate cognition. Nueva York: Oxford University Press.
Vygotsky, L. (1934). Thought and Language. Cambridge Mass: MIT Press.